n. 11
novembre 2011

 

Altri articoli disponibili

Italiano

Introduction to Bioethics
Fundamental Principles

edited by
MASSIMO PETRINI
 

trasp.gif (814 byte)

trasp.gif (814 byte)

trasp.gif (814 byte)

trasp.gif (814 byte)

In 1970, an oncologist, Van Rensslaer Potter publishes in the journal Perspectives in Biology and Medicine an article titled "Bioethics. The Science of Survival": the next year this is the first chapter of his book Bioethics. Bridge to the Future.


The rise of bioethics

Thus it was born the term bioethics to define a new discipline: the root bio represents the biological knowledge, the term ethical indicates the knowledge of the systems of human values. In his view, Potter was convinced that, for human survival, it is necessary to consider together the scientific and humanistic knowledge, since reading the scientific-technological progress as a threat to humanity and to the survival of life on earth. In fact, he refers to the bioethics as the science of survival, Science of Survival of the title of his article. Of course, the danger was not the progress, fully taken into account but the distortions that could arise from a misuse use of the new potential that the man had at his disposal.
The only solution would be to make a bridge (Bridge) between two cultures, scientific and moral; a bioethics that in view of Potter should consider the appropriateness of any scientific intervention on life in general. This requirement urged a Dutch origin famous obstetrician Andrè Hellegers who founded the Kennedy Institute of Ethics of Human Reproduction and Bioethics, in 1971, at Georgetown University in Washington, to create a dialogue between medicine, philosophy, ethics. Thus the term bioethics enters into the university world.
This view of bioethics, as a discipline applied to the biomedical sciences, influences the definition of the term that appeared in 1978 edition of Encyclopedia of Bioethics, published by the Kennedy Institute, where it appears as "systematic study of human conduct in the field of life and health sciences, as examined in the light of values
​​and moral principles."
In Italy, Msgr. Elio Sgreccia publics in 1988, Manuale di Bioetica (Handbook of Bioethics), republished several times, which still retains all its validity. In 1985 was established the Center for Bioethics, which will be joined in 1992 the Institute of Bioethics, Faculty of Medicine and Surgery, Catholic University of Sacred Heart. Together with the journal Medicina e Morale, whose director is the same Sgreccia, these initiatives and subsequent publications, which will extend their importance and influence in the international arena, significantly contributing to the debate on bioethics in Italy.


The object of study


       You can define the object of study of bioethics, in its aspects of human life, in the words of John Paul II's Encyclical Letter Evangelium vitae. The Pope insists that -along with threats of life such as murder, genocide, abortion, euthanasia and other historical forms of aggression against the human dignity- "the same medicine, which by its calling is directed to the defense and care of human life, in some sectors lends itself more widely to make acts against the person and thus deforms its face, contradicts itself and demeans the dignity of those who practice it"(EV 4).

These threats to human life arising from scientific progress that enables man to manipulate the arising of life. As reported by the Carta degli Operatori Sanitari (Letter to Health Care Workers) of the Pontifical Council for Pastoral Assistance to Health Care Workers, which states: "The more extensive knowledge of the genetic human inheritance (genome), identification and mapping of genes in action, with the possibility of transferring, modifying  or replacing them, opens new perspectives in medicine and simultaneously it poses new and delicate ethical problems"(No. 12).

New problems, however, are not just about birth, but the respect for human life at every stage and situation. Next to the scientific progress should also emphasize a different cultural ethos that gives less value on human life in terms of disability and old age; in the terminal phase of illness, to bring up the life as a "good stock" given to the personal will. Consequently, no less serious threats hang over the incurably ill and the dying in a social and cultural context which makes it more difficult to face and accept suffering, heightens the temptation to solve the problem of suffering by eliminating the root, by hastening death at the moment considered most suitable.

This is the context of bioethics, which reflects on meaning and value of human life and is itself as a discipline that aims to establish the basic criteria, because the interventions on human life are always attuned to man himself. According to John Paul II bioethics must be a precise and vigorous reaffirmation of the value of human life and its inviolability, an appeal in the name of God to respect, protect, love and serve life, every human life (cf. EV 5).


Some principles

Of course, in making ethical judgments, is a basic matter the reference to a system of principles on which to base arguments. Here we will refer to the most common systems: the system of American principles and the personalist bioethics.                                                                         When we speak of the principles’ system we are referring to T. L. Beauchamp and F.F. Childress, authors of the book Principles of Biomedical Ethics. These Authors propose the use of three principles -autonomy, beneficence / no-maleficence, justice- to resolve ethical controversies in practical situations.

The principle of autonomy emphasizes the freedom of the sick person who must be able to make an independent and informed consent,  choosing a medical treatment based on personal values. We can just think to the conscious rejection of care, communicating the truth about the real clinical conditions, the expression of requests for suspension of any treatment. Of course some objections may be if you think that there can be unlimited autonomy and, more importantly, if you think the impossibility of being able to express their choice in situations of non-awareness.

       The principle of beneficence/no-maleficence is rooted in the Hippocratic tradition, for which the physician agrees not to do anything harming his patient, but, through the beneficence, to prevent suffering and having to act for the patient’s good. No-maleficence calls clinical situations as aggressive treatment, ie the case of excessive therapy in now unrecoverable clinical situation of the sick person, and the beneficence recalls situations such as pain therapy and organ donation. The main difficulty is that this principle underlies the definition of good and evil in the absence of an ethical theory of reference, which is why you can create a conflict with the principle of autonomy when the idea of ​​the good doctor's care does not coincide with that of the patient.

The principle of justice, finally, on consideration of similar cases in the same way, streamlining operations in order to ensure medical care to each patient. Again you may object either on the possibility of clinical cases to assess or the same lack of an objective criterion which allows to determine the minimum of care and to ensure the priorities for the allocation of resources, often limited.


What Anthropology?

The criticism that move to these principles is that they are purely formal, because it is never said what we should strive virtually to autonomy and justice, or what is good or harm for the person. This was even more evident by the lack of a clear hierarchy among them, that enables to resolve conflict situations, for the absence of an anthropology of reference.
As part of the personalist model, found in the work of E. Sgreccia, the reference to the principles is within the unified theoric framework of the ontologically founded personalism, in which the center of the ethical choice is the unitary vision of the person. The principle is thus a key to read the individual real situations and the reference to the totality of the person determines a hierarchy of principles to avoid conflict situations.

Personalism sees a unity in the person, a unitotality of body and spirit that is its objective value. In front of each reflection, the person appears as a reference point, an aim and not a means, transcendent reality for society, economy, law. The Christian revelation, with the truth of creation, then gives to this personalist view a widening of horizons and values ​​that touches the divine.

The personalist bioethics analyzes, in determining the lawfulness of an action on man, three different components: biomedical data analysis in its scientifically checked foundation; anthropological and philosophical depth, ie the set of values ​​related to life, integrity and dignity of the person; solving the ethical problem, ie finding the values ​​to be protected and resources to be respected in relation to the person’s centrality and the hierarchy of values ​​in it harmonized. From the moment of conception until death, in every situation of suffering or health, the person must be a reference point and measure between the permissible and not permissible.
One other point: today the Ethics Committee, constituted of multi-disciplinary team of experts are called to solve the ethical problems that may arise in certain contexts (institutional care, research institutes, laboratories, etc.).

Massimo Petrini
Università Cattolica Gemelli – Roma
petrinimassimo.m@libero.it

 

 Torna indietro